Translate

Sunday, September 6, 2015

ACHILLES AND PRIAM

ACHILLES AND PRIAM

Is it possible that in Greece, that well-spring from where all have drunk, there was no love for enemies? Would-be modern pagans, enemies of the "Palestine superstition," claim that Greek thought has everything in it. In the spiritual life of the Occident, Greece is like China to the East, mother of all in­vention.

In the Ajax of Sophocles, famous Odysseus is moved to pity at the sight of a fallen enemy reduced to misery. In vain Athena herself, Hellenic wisdom personified in the sacred owl, reminds him that "the most delightful humor is to laugh at one's enemies." Ulysses is not convinced. "I pity him, although he is my enemy, because I see him so unfortunate, bound to an evil destiny; and looking at him, I think of myself. Because I see we are not other than ghosts, and unsubstantial shadows, all we who live. . . . It is not right to do evil to a dying man even if you hate him." It seems to me that we are here still very far away from love. Wily Ulysses is not wily enough to conceal the motive of his unnatural softening. He pities his enemy because he thinks of himself, remembers that evil could happen also to him, and he pardons his enemy only because he sees him dying and unfortunate.

A wiser man than Ulysses, the son of Sophroniscus, the stone cutter, asked himself, among many other questions, how the righteous man ought to treat his enemies. But reading the texts, we discover with astonishment two Socrates, of different opinions. The Socrates of the Memorabilia frankly accepts the common feeling. Friends are to be treated well and enemies’ ill, and thus it is better to anticipate one's enemies in do­ing ill: "The man most greatly to be praised," he says to Cherocrate, "is he who anticipates his enemies in hurtfulness and his friends in helpfulness." But Plato's Socrates does not accept the common opinion. He says to Crito, "Injustice should be rendered to no one in return for injustice; nor evil for evil whatever has been the injury that thou hast received." And he affirms the same principle in the Republic, adding in support that the bad are not made better through revenge. But the ruling idea in Socrates' head is the thought of justice, not the feeling of love. In no case should the righteous man do evil, out of self-respect (notice this), not out of affection towards his enemy. The bad man must punish himself, otherwise the Judges in the lower world will punish him after death. Aris­totle, the disciple of Plato, turns tranquilly back to the old Idea: "Not to resent offenses," he says in the Ethics to Nico-machus, "is the mark of a base and slavish man."

In Greece, therefore, there is little to the purpose for those who are looking for precedents for Christianity.

But in order to make us believe that Christianity existed be­fore Christ, those who deny Jesus, have found a rival to Jesus even in Rome, in the very palace of the Caesars. Seneca, the director of conscience to young gentlemen, leader of the fash­ionable cult of reformed stoicism; the abstract aristocrat never moved by the troubles of the poor; the proprietor who despises riches, and clutches them tightly, who affirms the equality be­tween free and slave; and owns slaves; the talented anatomist of ethics, of evils, of active vices, and complacent virtues; he who canalized the old doctrine of Crispus, dull but clear, towards the bay of refinement; moral Seneca they claim was a Christian without knowing it during Christ's very lifetime. Thumbing over his works (many were written after the death of Christ, for Seneca waited till he was sixty-five years old before committing suicide), they have found that "the wise man does not avenge but forgets affronts," and that "to imitate the Gods we should do good also to the ungrateful because the sun shines equally on the wicked and the seas bear up the pirate ship," and finally that "We must aid our ene­mies with a friendly hand." But the "forgetting" of the philo­sopher is not "forgiveness"; and "relief" can be philanthropy but is not love. The imperious, the stoic, the Pharisee; the philosopher proud of his philosophy, the righteous man com­placent over his righteousness, can despise the insults of the small, the pricks of enemies, and through pride of liberal giving and to win admiration can stoop to give a loaf to a hungry enemy in order to humiliate him more harshly from the heights of perfection. But that bread was prepared with the leaven of vanity and that would-be friendly hand could never have dried a tear or dressed a wound.

The world of antiquity did not know love. It knew passion for a woman, friendship for a friend, justice for the citizen, hospitality for the foreigner; but it did not know love. Zeus protected pilgrims and strangers; he who knocked at the Grecian door was not denied meat, a cup of wine, and a bed. The poor were to be covered, the weak helped, the mourning consoled with fair words; but the men of antiquity did not know love, love that suffers, that shares another's sorrow, love for all who suffer and are neglected, love for the poor, the lowly, the outlawed, the maligned, the downtrodden, the abandoned; love for all, love which knows no difference between fellow-citizens and strangers, between fair and foul, be­tween criminal and philosopher, between brother and enemy.

In the last stanza of the Iliad we see an old man, a mourner, a father who kisses the hand of his most terrible enemy, of the man who has killed his sons, who has just killed his most loved son. Priam. The old king, head of the rich, ruined city, father of fifty sons, kneels at the feet of Achilles, the greatest hero, and the unhappy among the Greeks, son of the Sea-God­dess, avenger of Patroclus, slayer of Hector. The white head of the kneeling old man is bowed before the proud youth of the victor, and Priam mourns for the slain, strongest, and fairest, most loved of all his fifty sons, and kisses the hand of the slayer! "Thou also," he says, "hast a grey-haired, failing, de­fenseless, far-distant father. In the name of thy father's love, give me back at least the dead body of my son."

Achilles, the fierce, the wild, the slaughterer, puts the sup­pliant gently on one side and begins to weep; and both of them, the two enemies, the conqueror and the conquered, the father bereaved of his son and the son who will never see his father again, the white-haired old man and the golden-haired youth both weep, drawn together for the first time by sorrow. The others round about gaze at them silent and astounded: we ourselves after fifty centuries are shaken by their grief.

But in the kiss of Priam there is no pardon, there is no love. This king humbles himself to obtain a difficult and unusual favor. If a God had not inspired him he would not have stirred from Ilium; and Achilles does not weep for dead Hec­tor, for weeping Priam, for the powerful man who is brought to humble himself, for the enemy who is brought to kiss the hand of the slayer. He weeps over his lost friend; over Patrocles, dearer to him than all other men; over Peleus, left at Phthia; over his father, whom he will never more embrace, for he knows that his young days are numbered. And he gives back to the father the dead body of his son—that body which he has dragged for so many days in the dust—because it is the will of Zeus, not because his hunger of vengeance is stilled. Both of them weep for themselves; the kiss of Priam is a harsh necessity, the restitution of Achilles is obedience to the Gods. In the noblest heroic world of antiquity there is no place for that love which destroys hate and takes the place of hate, for love stronger than the strength of hate, more passionate, more im­placable, more faithful, for love which is not forgetfulness of wrong, but love of wrong, because wrong is a misfortune for him who commits it rather than for him who suffers.* There is no place for love for enemies in the world of antiquity.

Jesus was the first to speak of such love, to conceive of such love. This love was not known till the Sermon on the Mount. This is the greatest and the most original of Jesus' concep­tions. Of all His teachings this was the newest to men, this is still His greatest innovation. It is new even to us, new because it is not understood, not imitated, not obeyed; infinitely eternal like truth.

No comments:

Post a Comment